References

Andersen, H., & Wagenknecht, S. (2013). Epistemic dependence in interdisciplinary groups. Synthese, 190(11), 1881—1898.

Ankeny, R., Chang, H., Boumans, M., & Boon, M. (2011). Introduction: Philosophy of science in practice. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 1(3), 303-307.

Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. New York: Routledge.

Bergin, L. A. (2002). Testimony, epistemic difference, and privilege: How feminist epistemology can improve our understanding of the communication ofknowledge. Social Epistemology, 16 (3), 197-213.

Callebaut, W. (Ed.). (1993). Taking the naturalistic turn: Or how real philosophy of science is done. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Calvert, J., & Fujimura, J. H. (2011). Calculating life? Duelling discourses in interdisciplinary systems biology. Studies In History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 42(2), 155-163.

Cheon, H. (2014). In what sense is scientific knowledge collective knowledge? Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 44(4), 407-423.

Cohen, S. (1986). Knowledge and context. The Journal of Philosophy, §3(10), 574-583.

Collins, H. (2013). Three dimensions of expertise. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 12(2), 253-273.

Collins, H., & Evans, R. (2007). Rethinking expertise. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Craig, E. (1990). Knowledge and the state of nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

de Ridder, J. (2014). Epistemic dependence and collective scientific knowledge. Synthese, 191(1), 37-53.

Fantl, J. (2012). Knowledge how. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2012 ed.). Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/win2012/entries/knowledge- how/

Fricker, E. (2006b). Testimony and epistemic autonomy. In J. Lackey & E. Sosa (Eds.), The epistemology of testimony (pp. 225-250). Oxford: Clarendon.

Fuller, S. (1988). Social epistemology. Bloomington: Indiana Unversity Press.

Giere, R. N. (1985). Philosophy of science naturalized. Philosophy of Science, 52(3), 331-356.

Giere, R. N. (1988). Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Gilbert, M. (1989). On social facts. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Gilbert, M. (2004). Collective epistemology. Episteme, 1(2), 95—107.

Goddiksen, M. (2014). Clarifying interactional and contributory expertise. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 47, 111—117.

Goldman, A. I. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Goldman, A. I. (1999). Knowledge in a social world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Goldman, A. I. (2011). Reliabilism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2011 ed.). Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/spr2011/entries/reliabilism/ (Last accessed on January 3, 2014)

Greco, J. (2001). Virtues and rules in epistemology. In L. Zagzebski & A. Fair- weather (Eds.), Virtue epistemology: Essays on epistemic virtue and responsibility (pp. 117-141). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Green, D. E. (1954). Group research. Science, 119(3092), 444-445.

Griffiths, P., & Stotz, K. (2008). Experimental philosophy of science. Philosophy Compass, 3(3), 507-521.

Haack, S. (2009). Evidence and inquiry: a pragmatist reconstruction of epistemology. (2nd, expanded ed.). New York: Prometheus Books.

Hardwig, J. (1985). Epistemic dependence. The Journal of Philosophy, 82(7), 335349.

Hardwig, J. (1991). The role of trust in knowledge. The Journal of Philosophy, 88(12), 693-708.

Ichikawa, J. J., & Steup, M. (2013). The analysis of knowledge. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2013 ed.). Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/knowledge-analysis/ (Last accessed on October 16, 2013.)

Kastenhofer, K. (2013). Two sides of the same coin? The (techno)epistemic cultures of systems and synthetic biology. Studies In History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44(2), 130-140.

Knobe, J., & Nichols, S. (2008). An experimental philosophy manifesto. In J. Knobe & S. Nichols (Eds.), Experimental philosophy (pp. 3-16). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Kusch, M. (2002). Knowledge by agreement: The programme of communitarian epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Leonelli, S. (2007). Weed for thought: Using Arabidopsis thaliana to understand plant biology (Doctoral dissertation, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam). Retrieved from http://hdl.handle.net/1871/10703 (Last accessed on September 18, 2013.)

Leonelli, S. (2010a). Documenting the emergence of bio-ontologies: Or, why researching bioinformatics requires HPSSB. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 32(1), 105—126.

Longino, H. E. (1990). Science as social knowledge: values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Longino, H. E. (2002). The fate of knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Machery, E., & O’Neill, E. (Eds.). (2014). Current controversies in experimental philosophy. New York: Routledge.

Nelson, L. H. (1990). Who knows: From Quine to a feminist empiricism. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

Nersessian, N. J. (1984). Faraday to Einstein: Constructing meaning in scientific theories. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Nersessian, N. J. (2006). The cognitive-cultural systems of the research laboratory. Organization Studies, 27(1), 125—145.

Nersessian, N. J., Kurz-Milcke, E., Newstetter, W. C., & Davies, J. (2003). Research laboratories as evolving distributed cognitive systems. In R. Alter- mann & D. Kirsh (Eds.), Proceedings of the twenty-fifth annual conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 857—862). Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Nickles, T. (1995). Philosophy of science and history of science. Osiris, 10, 139— 163.

Osbeck, L. M., & Nersessian, N. J. (2010). Forms of positioning in interdisciplinary science practice and their epistemic effects. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 40(2), 136—161.

Osbeck, L. M., & Nersessian, N. J. (2015). Prolegomena to an empirical philosophy of science. In S. Wagenknecht, N. J. Nersession, & H. Andersen (Eds.), Empirical philosophy of science. Introducing qualitative methods into philosophy of science (pp. 13—35). Dordrecht: Springer.

Osbeck, L. M., Nersessian, N. J., Malone, K. R., & Newstetter, W. C. (2011). Science as psychology: Sense-making and identity in science practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Polanyi, M. (1962). Personal knowledge: Towards a post-critical philosophy. (Corrected Edition. Originally published in 1958. ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Popper, K. R. (1972). Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Pritchard, D. (2000). Closure and context. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78(2), 275-280.

Quine, W. V. (1969). Epistemology naturalized. In Ontological relativity and other essays (pp. 69—90). New York: Columbia University Press.

Rehg, W., & Staley, K. W. (2008). The CDF collaboration and argumentation theory: The role of process in objective knowledge. Perspectives on Science,

16 (1), 1-25.

Riesch, H. (2010). Simple or simplistic? Scientists’ views on Occam’s Razor. Theoria, 67, 75-90.

Rouse, J. (1996). Engaging science: How to understand its practices philosophically. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Rouse, J. (2002). How scientific practices matter. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Ryle, G. (1971). Knowing how and knowing that. In Collected papers (Vol. 2, pp. 212-25). Barnes and Nobles. (Originally published in 1946.)

Rysiew, P. (2016). Epistemic contextualism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2016 ed.). http://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/spr2016/entries/contextualism-epistemology/

Schickore, J. (2011). More thoughts on HPS: Another 20 years later. Perspectives on Science, 19(4), 453-481.

Schmitt, F. F. (1994). The justification of group beliefs. In F. F. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializing epistemology: The social dimensions of knowledge (pp. 257-287). Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

Soler, L. (2011). Tacit aspects of experimental practices: analytical tools and epistemological consequences. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 1(1), 393-433.

Soler, L., Zwart, S., Lynch, M., & Israel-Jost, V. (Eds.). (2014). Science after the practice turn in the philosophy, history and social studies of science. New York: Routledge.

Staley, K. W. (2007). Evidential collaborations: Epistemic and pragmatic considerations in ‘group belief’. Social Epistemology, 21(3), 249-266.

Toon, A. (2012). Models as make-believe. Imagination, fiction and scientific representation. Basingstoke, New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

Vendler, Z. (1972). Res cogitans: An essay in rational psychology. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Wagenknecht, S., Nersessian, N. J., & Andersen, H. (2015). Empirical philosophy of science: Introducing qualitative methods into philosophy of science (introduction). In S. Wagenknecht, N. J. Nersession, & H. Andersen (Eds.), Empirical philosophy of science. Introducing qualitative methods into philosophy of science (pp. 1-10). Dordrecht: Springer.

Weinberg, A. M. (1961). Impact of large-scale science on the United States.

Science, 134(3473), 161-164.

Welbourne, M. (2001). Knowledge. Chesham: Acumen.

Wray, B. K. (2001). Collective belief and acceptance. Synthese, 129(3), 319-333. Zagzebski, L. (1996). Virtues of the mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

 
Source
< Prev   CONTENTS   Source   Next >